One of the most elegant features of mathematical logic is how it handles internal variables - those temporary objects we need while building larger mathematical structures. Understanding how to properly use existential quantification for these variables is useful when writing precise mathematical definitions.
Consider a simple example: how do we formally define function composition?
Intuitively, when we compose two functions
Let's start with a basic definition of a total function:
Now, for composition, we need three sets:
- the domain of
$f$ - some intermediate set
- the codomain of
$g$
The intermediate set must serve as both the codomain of
Here's where existential quantification shines. Instead of trying to explicitly construct the intermediate set, we can assert its existence:
Meaning "a composition is total is the same as there exists a middle set C where f is total from A to C and g is total from C to B."
This definition elegantly captures several key ideas:
- There must be some set
$C$ that works as our intermediate set -
$C$ is bound within the scope of the composition - We don't need to specify exactly what
$C$ is
Existential quantification is perfect for internal variables because it:
- Binds the variable to a specific scope
- Asserts existence without over specifying
- Maintains mathematical rigor
- Preserves flexibility in implementation
Consider the alternative: trying to explicitly define the intermediate set as
While this works, it's unnecessarily restrictive.
We're forcing
For mathematicians, consider f mapping to positive numbers and g defined over all reals. With explicit construction, C must be exactly f's positive outputs, but g might be well-defined on all reals (like g(x) = x + 1). The existential approach naturally allows C to be the real numbers.
For programmers, imagine f returning integers 0-100 (percentages) and g computing averages. Instead of forcing C to be exactly {0,1,2,...,100}, the existential approach allows C to be float or double, matching how we'd actually implement these functions and avoiding unnecessary type conversions.
In both cases, allowing C to be a superset matches how we naturally work with functions, avoids artificial restrictions, and leads to cleaner implementations while preserving the essential meaning.
Existential quantification solves the problem of internal variables by asserting their existence without constraining their exact form.
This is simpler and more general than explicitly constructing them.
As we've seen with function composition,
letting
Have you found other examples where existential quantification simplifies definitions? Share your insights!
#MathematicalLogic #ProgrammingLanguages #TypeTheory #FormalMethods #CompSci