Skip to content

Instantly share code, notes, and snippets.

@adept
Last active December 19, 2017 00:51
Show Gist options
  • Save adept/70aade7f5ecf3b6a295db51c080dcdf0 to your computer and use it in GitHub Desktop.
Save adept/70aade7f5ecf3b6a295db51c080dcdf0 to your computer and use it in GitHub Desktop.
{-
Lecture 1 on cubicaltt (Cubical Type Theory)
--------------------------------------------------------------------------
Anders Mörtberg
This is the first lecture in a series of hands-on lectures about
cubicaltt given at Inria Sophia Antipolis.
To try the system clone the github repository and follow the
compilation instructions at:
https://github.com/mortberg/cubicaltt
This file is a cubicaltt file that can be found in:
lectures/lecture1.ctt
To load this file either type C-c C-l after opening it in emacs
(assuming that the cubicaltt emacs mode has been configured properly),
or use the cubical executable in a terminal:
$ cubical lectures/lecture1.ctt
if the system has been installed using cabal, or
$ ./cubical lectures/lecture1.ctt
if the system has been compiled using make. This will start an
interactive cubical process where one can query the system and see
error messages, this will be referred to as the REPL
(read-eval-print-loop) in what follows. To see a list of available
commands to the executable use the --help flag and to see available
commands in the REPL write :h.
The basic type system is based on Mini-TT:
"A simple type-theoretic language: Mini-TT" (2009)
Thierry Coquand, Yoshiki Kinoshita, Bengt Nordström and Makoto Takeya
In "From Semantics to Computer Science; Essays in Honour of Gilles Kahn"
Mini-TT is a variant Martin-Löf type theory with datatypes. cubicaltt
extends Mini-TT with:
o Path types
o Compositions
o Glue types
o Id types
o Some higher inductive types
In the first lecture I will cover the basic type theory and a bit of
the Path types. The Cubical Type Theory has been written up in:
"Cubical Type Theory: a constructive interpretation of the
univalence axiom"
Cyril Cohen, Thierry Coquand, Simon Huber and Anders Mörtberg
https://arxiv.org/abs/1611.02108
The lectures will follow the structure of the paper rather closely,
there are some small differences between the implementation and the
system in the paper and I will try to point these out as I go
along. One reason for the differences is that the implementation was
done before the paper. While writing the paper we found various
simplifications and different ways of organizing things. Having a
working implementation to experiment while designing the type theory
was a lot of fun and very useful.
The main goal of Cubical Type Theory is to provide a computational
justification (or meaning explanations) for notions in Homotopy Type
Theory and Univalent Foundations, in particular Voevodsky's Univalence
Axiom. This means that we define a type theory without axioms in which
univalence is provable. One consequence of this is that we get a type
theory extending intensional type theory with extensional features
(functional and propositional extensionality, quotients, etc.). We
want this type theory to have good properties, so far the Cubical Type
Theory in the paper has been proved to satisfy canonicity in:
"Canonicity for Cubical Type Theory"
Simon Huber
https://arxiv.org/abs/1607.04156
It should be possible to extend this to a normalization result and to
also prove decidability of type checking (the implementation provides
some empirical evidence for this).
The basic type theory on which cubicaltt is based has Pi and Sigma
types, a universe U, datatypes, recursive definitions and mutually
recursive definitions (in particular inductive-recursive
definitions). Note that general datatypes and (mutually recursive)
definitions are not part of the version in the paper.
The implementation is kept as small as possible in order to make it
easier to understand and debug. Because of this there is no
unification (so no implicit arguments), no termination checker and we
assume U : U. The implementation is hence inconsistent, but this is
not a problem as long as one is careful :-)
The implementation is written in Haskell and consists of the following
files:
- Exp.cf: grammar for automatically generating a lexer and parser
using BNFC. The auto-generated datatype for the concrete syntax is
in Exp/Abs.hs
- CTT.hs: datatypes representing expressions and values used in the
system, in particular this contains the internal representation of
terms and types.
- Resolver.hs: preprocessor doing a basic translation from the
concrete syntax defined in Exp/Abs.hs to the abstract syntax defined
in CTT.hs (i.e. translating what the user writes to what the system
uses internally). This removes some syntactic sugar (for example
lambdas with multiple arguments is turned into multiple single
argument lambdas) and other similar things.
- Connections.hs: datatypes and typeclasses used by the typechecker
and evaluator (basic operations on the interval and face lattice,
systems, etc...).
- Typechecker.hs: the bidirectional typechecker.
- Eval.hs: the evaluator, this is the main part of the
implementation. For example this is where all of the computations of
compositions and Kan fillings happen. This also contains the
conversion function used in the typechecker.
- Main.hs: The read-eval-print-loop (REPL).
These constitute around 3200loc which is not too bad keeping in mind
that Cubical Type Theory is a fairly complicated type theory.
Note also that Connections.hs contains a typeclass called Nominal.
This is because of the connection between the original cubical set
model:
"A model of type theory in cubical sets" by Marc Bezem, Thierry
Coquand and Simon Huber.
http://www.cse.chalmers.se/~coquand/mod1.pdf
and nominal sets with 01 substitutions:
"An Equivalent Presentation of the Bezem-Coquand-Huber Category of
Cubical Sets"
Andrew Pitts
https://arxiv.org/abs/1401.7807
Before implementing cubicaltt, so around 2013-2014, we implemented a
system called cubical
https://github.com/simhu/cubical
based on the ideas from the two above papers. This type theory had
uninterpreted constants, these then got interpreted in the original
cubical set model where they had a computational meaning. This
implementation provided the basis for the cubicaltt development which
is why some ideas that proved to be very useful for the cubical
implementation are also in cubicaltt (in particular the Nominal class
is still there, but with some modifications).
The concrete syntax of cubicaltt is similar to that of Haskell and
Agda. For example the syntax for comments is:
-- This is a single line comment
and this whole introduction is a multiline comment.
After this long introduction it is finally time for some cubicaltt
code!
-}
-- In cubicaltt all files must start with:
module lecture1 where
-- However this is just indicating the beginning of the file, there is
-- no module system.
{-
The examples/ directory contains a lot of examples implemented in
cubicaltt. If this file would be there one could import the theory on
natural numbers by writing:
import nat
However as this lecture will be self-contained no imports are
necessary. Note that the import mechanism is very simple and recursive
so that if I import nat then it will automatically import everything
nat depends on (like prelude.ctt).
-}
-- The identity function can be written like this:
idfun : (A : U) (a : A) -> A = \(A : U) (a : A) -> a
-- Or even better like this:
idfun (A : U) (a : A) : A = a
-- The syntax for Pi types is like in Agda, so (x : A) -> B
-- corresponds to Pi (x : A). B or forall (x : A), B.
-- Lambda abstraction is written similariy to Pi types: \(x : A) -> x
-- Note that the second idfun shadows the first, so when one uses
-- idfun later this will refer to the last defined one.
{-
There are some special keywords that cannot be used as identifiers:
module, where, let, in, split, with, mutual, import, data, hdata,
undefined, PathP, comp, transport, fill, Glue, glue, unglue, U,
opaque, transparent, transparent_all, Id, idC, idJ
-}
-- Datatypes can be introduced by:
data bool = true | false
-- We can now compute things in the REPL:
-- > idfun bool true
-- EVAL: true
-- Note that inductive families are not definable directly, however it
-- should be possible to encode them (using either Path types or Id
-- types).
-- Note: the constructors are not definitions, so typing:
--
-- > true
--
-- in the REPL fails.
-- TODO: Maybe this should be changed?
-- Functions out of inductive types can be defined by case analysis
-- using split:
not : bool -> bool = split
true -> false
false -> true
-- Note that the order of the cases matter and have to be the same as
-- in the datatype declaration. The list of cases must be exhaustive
-- and there is no way to make a "default" case (like _ in Haskell).
-- Local definitions can be made using let-in or where, just like in
-- Haskell. Note that split can only appear on the top-level, local
-- splits can be done but then one needs to annotate them with the
-- type using the syntax in the false branch below:
or : bool -> bool -> bool = split
true -> let constTrue (_ : bool) : bool = b
where
b : bool = true
in constTrue
false -> split@(bool -> bool) with
true -> true
false -> false
-- Note the _, this is a name that is used for arguments that do not
-- appear in the rest of the term (in particular one cannot refer to a
-- variable called _).
-- Note also that the syntax is indentation sensitive (like in
-- Haskell), so the following does not parse:
--
-- foo : bool = let output : bool =
-- true
-- in output
-- Sigma types are built-in and written as (x : A) * B:
Sigma (A : U) (B : A -> U) : U = (x : A) * B x
-- First and second projections are given by .1 and .2:
fst (A : U) (B : A -> U) (p : Sigma A B) : A = p.1
snd (A : U) (B : A -> U) (p : Sigma A B) : B (fst A B p) = p.2
-- Pairing is written (a,b):
pair (A : U) (B : A -> U) (a : A) (b : B a) : Sigma A B = (a,b)
-- The reason Sigma types are built-in and not defined as a datatype
-- is that we want surjective pairing. So if we have p : Sigma A B
-- then p is convertible to (p.1,p.2). We could have achieved this by
-- implementing eta for single constructor datatypes, but having
-- built-in Sigma types seemed easier to implement.
-- We have also eta for Pi-types, so given f : (x : A) -> B we get
-- that f is convertible with \(x : A) -> f x.
-- Datatypes can be recursive:
data nat = zero
| suc (n : nat)
-- and definitions can be recursive:
add (m : nat) : nat -> nat = split
zero -> m
suc n -> suc (add m n)
-- As there is no termination checker one can incidentally write a
-- loop (and use this to prove False). So one has to be a bit careful!
-- Definitions can also be mutual:
mutual
even : nat -> bool = split
zero -> true
suc n -> odd n
odd : nat -> bool = split
zero -> false
suc n -> even n
-- This can be used to do induction-recursion:
mutual
data V = N | pi (a : V) (b : T a -> V)
T : V -> U = split
N -> nat
pi a b -> (x : T a) -> T (b x)
-- WARNING: This feature has not been exhaustively tested.
-- Datatypes with parameters can be defined by:
data list (A : U) = nil
| cons (a : A) (l : list A)
head (A : U) (a : A) : list A -> A = split
nil -> a
cons x _ -> x
tail (A : U) (a : A) : list A -> list A = split
nil -> nil
cons _ tl -> tl
-- Now it's finally time for some cubical stuff!
--------------------------------------------------------------------
-- Path types
{-
We would like to prove: (b : bool) -> not (not b) = b
But what is =?
From HoTT we have the intuition that equality corresponds to paths, in
Cubical Type Theory we take this literally. We assume an abstract
interval II (this is not a type for deep reasons!) and a path in a
type A can then be thought of as a function II -> A. As II is not a
type we introduce a Path type called PathP together with a binder,
written <i>, for path-abstraction and a path-application written p @ r
where r is some element of the interval.
-}
-- As in the Cubical Type Theory paper the type PathP (written Path in
-- the paper!) is heterogeneous. The homogeneous Path type can be
-- defined by:
Path (A : U) (a b : A) : U = PathP (<_> A) a b
{-
A term p : Path A a b corresponds to a path in A:
p
a ------> b
So the above goal can now be written:
(b : bool) -> Path bool (not (not b)) b
-}
{-
The simplest path possible is the reflexivity path:
<i> a
a -------> a
The intuition is that
<i> a
corresponds to
\(i : II) -> a
So <i> a is a function out of II that is constantly a. (But as II
isn't a type we cannot write that as a lambda abstraction and we need
a special syntax for it)
-}
refl (A : U) (a : A) : Path A a a = <i> a
-- A more concrete path:
truePath : Path bool true true = <i> true
-- The interval II has two end-points 0 and 1. By applying a path to 0
-- or 1 we obtain the end-points of the path:
face0 (A : U) (a b : A) (p : Path A a b) : A = p @ 0
-- We can now prove: (b : bool) -> Path bool (not (not b)) b.
-- The proof is done by case analysis on b and in both cases it is
-- proved by reflexivity.
notK : (b : bool) -> Path bool (not (not b)) b = split
true -> <i> true
false -> <i> false
{-
One can write proofs and programs interactively using holes, to try
this write:
notK : (b : bool) -> Path bool (not (not b)) b = split
true -> ?
false -> ?
Note that this only works in a position where the typechecker is
trying to check that a term u has type T, so it doesn't work when the
typechecker tries to infer the type of u (recall that the typechecker
is bidirectional). If we would have general type inference and
unification we could do this a lot better like in Agda.
TODO: The pretty-printing is not very nice. Pull-requests improving
this would be very appreciated :-)
-}
-- Using Path types we get a simple proof of cong:
cong (A B : U) (f : A -> B) (a b : A) (p : Path A a b) :
Path B (f a) (f b) = <i> f (p @ i)
-- To see why this makes sense compute this at i=0 and i=1.
-- Exercise: cong for binary functions
congbin (A B C : U) (f : A -> B -> C) (a a' : A) (b b' : B)
(p : Path A a a') (q : Path B b b') :
Path C (f a b) (f a' b') = <i> f (p@i) (q@i)
-- Note that undefined can only be used at the top-level to introduce
-- definitions without bodies, much like axioms in Coq. The reason
-- that it only works at the top-level is that we need to know the
-- type. We could have a version of undefined that is annotated with
-- the type (similar to what we have for split), but this hasn't been
-- implemented yet. Note that it is often useful to define a local
-- definition using let-in or where and keep the body of it undefined
-- when trying to prove complicated things.
-- We get a short proof of function extensionality using Path types:
funExt (A B : U) (f g : A -> B)
(p : (x : A) -> Path B (f x) (g x)) :
Path (A -> B) f g = <i> \(a : A) -> (p a) @ i
{-
To see that this makes sense compute the end-points of the path:
(<i> \(a : A) -> (p a) @ i) @ 0 = \(a : A) -> (p a) @ 0
= \(a : A) -> f a
= f
Note that the last equality follows by eta for Pi.
-}
-- Exercise: dependent function extensionality
funExt (A : U) (B : A -> U) (f g : (x : A) -> B x)
(p : (x : A) -> Path (B x) (f x) (g x)) :
Path ((x : A) -> B x) f g = undefined
-- Exercise: function extensionality for binary functions
funExt2 (A B C : U) (f g : A -> B -> C)
(p : (x : A) (y : B) -> Path C (f x y) (g x y)) :
Path (A -> B -> C) f g = undefined
-- Using function extensionality we can prove: not o not = id
compf (f g : bool -> bool) : bool -> bool =
\(b : bool) -> g (f b)
-- WARNING: we couldn't have called the above function comp as comp is
-- a reserved keyword.
notK' : Path (bool -> bool) (compf not not) (idfun bool) =
<i> \(b : bool) -> notK b @ i
-- Exercise: even n = odd (suc n)
evenodd : (n : nat) -> Path bool (even n) (odd (suc n)) = split
zero -> <i> true
suc n -> <i> odd n
and : bool -> bool -> bool = split
true -> \(x:bool) -> x
false -> let constFalse (_:bool) : bool = false
in constFalse
addzero : (x:nat) -> Path nat x (add zero x) = split
zero -> <i> zero
suc x -> <i> suc (addzero x @ i)
even_plus_even : (n m : nat) -> Path bool (and (even n) (even m)) (even(add n m)) = split
zero -> \(m:nat) -> <i> even (addzero m@i)
suc n -> \(m:nat) -> ?
{-
That's all for the first lecture. Next time we will look at:
- More things from II: symmetry (-) and connections (/\ and \/)
- Compositions, transport, fill and how these can be used to prove the
elimination principle for Path types. In particular how to prove
transitivity of path types:
compPath (A : U) (a b c : A) (p : Path A a b) (q : Path A b c) : Path A a c =
and that we can substitute Path equal elements:
subst (A : U) (P : A -> U) (a b : A) (p : Path A a b) (e : P a) : P b =
-}
Checking: idfun
Checking: idfun
Checking: bool
Checking: not
Checking: or
Checking: constTrue
Checking: b
Checking: Sigma
Checking: fst
Checking: snd
Checking: pair
Checking: nat
Checking: add
Checking: even odd
Checking: V T
Checking: list
Checking: head
Checking: tail
Checking: Path
Checking: refl
Checking: truePath
Checking: face0
Checking: notK
Checking: cong
Checking: congbin
Checking: funExt
Checking: funExt
Checking: funExt2
Checking: compf
Checking: notK'
Checking: evenodd
Checking: and
Checking: constFalse
Checking: addzero
Checking: even_plus_even
Type checking failed: path endpoints don't match for even ((addzero m) @ i), got (even m,even (add zero m)), but expected (lecture1_L498_C6 (even m),even (add zero m))
Sign up for free to join this conversation on GitHub. Already have an account? Sign in to comment