Skip to content

Instantly share code, notes, and snippets.

@tbelaire
Created March 14, 2016 19:14
Show Gist options
  • Save tbelaire/21a092c40970aa2cde1e to your computer and use it in GitHub Desktop.
Save tbelaire/21a092c40970aa2cde1e to your computer and use it in GitHub Desktop.
(**************************************************************)
(** * Coq for POPL Folk *)
(**************************************************************)
(** A streamlined interactive tutorial on fundamentals of Coq,
focusing on a minimal set of features needed for developing
programming language metatheory.
Mostly developed by Aaron Bohannon, with help from Benjamin
Pierce, Dimitrios Vytiniotis, and Steve Zdancewic.
*)
(**************************************************************)
(** * Contents
- Getting Started
- Definitions
- Proofs
-- Working with Implication and Universal Quantification
-- Working with Definitions
-- Working with Conjunction and Disjunction
-- Reasoning by Cases and Induction
-- Working with Existential Quantification
-- Working with Negation
-- Working with Equality
-- Reasoning by Inversion
-- Additional Important Tactics
-- Basic Automation
-- Functions and Conversion
- Solutions to Exercises
*)
(**************************************************************)
(**************************************************************)
(** * Getting Started *)
(**************************************************************)
(** To get started...
- Install Coq (from the Download page of the main Coq web
site)
- Install an IDE: either CoqIDE (from the same page) or
Proof General (use Google to find it).
- Which should you choose? Their command sets are similar,
so basically the trade-offs are simple:
-- Proof General is an extension of Emacs (or XEmacs,
if you prefer), while CoqIDE uses a simpler
point-and-click model of editing.
-- PG is pretty easy to install; CoqIDE is very easy
to install if you can find a pre-built version for
the OS you are running on but can be a little tricky
to build from scratch because it has lots of
dependencies.
- Familiarize yourself with the most important commands
-- If you are using PG, try this:
--- Open this file and check that the mode line says
something like "coq Holes Scripting"
--- Go down a few pages and do C-C C-return. Notice
that the part of the file above the cursor
changes color (and becomes read-only),
indicating that it has been sent to Coq.
--- Come back here and do C-C C-return again
--- You now know all you really need to navigate in
this file and send parts of it to Coq, but there
are some other navigation commands that are
sometimes more convenient. To see a couple
more, do C-C C-n several times and observe the
result; then do C-C C-u a couple of times and
observe the result.
-- If you are using CoqIDE, try this:
--- Open this file.
--- Scroll down a few pages.
--- Hover the mouse over each the buttons at the top
of the window; this will make the "tool tips"
appear so you can see which is which.
--- Press the "Go to cursor" button. Observe what
happens.
--- Press the forward and backward buttons a few
times. Observe.
--- Scroll back to here again and start reading.
- Open the Coq reference manual (from the Documentation
page of the Coq web site) in a web browser. Spend 30
seconds looking over the table of contents to get an idea
what's there. (There is no need to actually read
anything now.)
*)
(**************************************************************)
(** * Definitions *)
(**************************************************************)
(** In this file, we will be working with a very simple language
of expressions over natural numbers and booleans. First we
need to define the datatype of terms.
The [Inductive] keyword defines a new inductive type. We
name our new type [tm] and declare that [tm] lives in the
sort [Set]. Types in [Set] are datatypes, which can be used
just like those in standard programming languages. After
the inductive definition, the global environment contains
the name of the newly defined type, along with the names of
all of the constructors. Coq also automatically defines a
few operators for eliminating values of the new type
([tm_rec], [tm_ind], etc.); we can ignore these for the time
being, since we will not need to use them directly.
*)
Inductive tm : Set :=
| tm_true : tm
| tm_false : tm
| tm_if : tm -> tm -> tm -> tm
| tm_zero : tm
| tm_succ : tm -> tm
| tm_pred : tm -> tm
| tm_iszero : tm -> tm.
(** Next, we want to designate some of our [tm] expressions as
"values" in our object language. Mathematically, the
property of being a value is a unary relation over [tm]s.
The definition of the unary relation [value] will be built
from the definition of two auxiliary relations: [bvalue] for
the set of boolean values and [nvalue] for the set of
numerical values.
We define n-ary relations in Coq much as we do on paper --
by giving a set of inference rules that can be used to
justify the membership of a tuple in the relation. The
definition of such an inference system also uses the keyword
[Inductive]. Although this is exactly the same device we
used to build the set [tm], in this case we want to do
something slightly different: we will be using it to
inductively defining the structures (derivation trees) that
justify the membership of a tuple in a relation, rather than
directly defining a set inductively. These derivation trees
will need to be given a dependent type in order to ensure
that only correct derivation trees can be built. It is
possible to view their type as a datatype such as [tm];
however, it is more natural to interpret it as a
proposition, so it will be declared to live in [Prop]
instead of [Set]. [Prop] is parallel to [Set] in the sort
hierarchy, but types in [Prop] can be thought of as logical
propositions rather than datatypes. The inhabitants of
types in [Prop] can be thought of as proofs rather than
programs.
The unary relations [bvalue] and [nvalue] are defined by
very simple inference systems, each having just two rules.
After defining these inference systems, [bvalue] and
[nvalue] will each be a family of types indexed by elements
of [tm]. We can build inhabitants of some (but not all) of
the types in these families with the constructors from our
inductive definition. Semantically, we consider the
proposition [bvalue t] to be true if it is inhabited and
false if it is not. (It is worth noting at this point that,
by default, Coq's logic is constructive and [P \/ not P] is
provable for some [P] but not for others. However, it is
sound to add the law of the excluded middle as an axiom, if
desired.)
*)
Inductive bvalue : tm -> Prop :=
| b_true : bvalue tm_true
| b_false : bvalue tm_false.
Inductive nvalue : tm -> Prop :=
| n_zero : nvalue tm_zero
| n_succ : forall t,
nvalue t ->
nvalue (tm_succ t).
(** The [Definition] keyword is used for defining non-recursive
functions (including 0-ary functions, i.e., constants).
Here we define the unary predicate [value] using disjunction
on propositions (written [\/]).
Note: It is not actually necessary to provide the types of
the arguments nor the return type when they can easily be
inferred; for example, the annotations [: tm] and [: Prop]
are optional here.
*)
Definition value (t : tm) : Prop :=
bvalue t \/ nvalue t.
(** Having defined [tm]s and [value]s, we can define a
call-by-value operational semantics of our language by
giving a definition of the single-step evaluation of one
term to another. We give this as an inductively defined
binary relation.
*)
Inductive eval : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| e_iftrue : forall t2 t3,
eval (tm_if tm_true t2 t3) t2
| e_iffalse : forall t2 t3,
eval (tm_if tm_false t2 t3) t3
| e_if : forall t1 t1' t2 t3,
eval t1 t1' ->
eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) (tm_if t1' t2 t3)
| e_succ : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ t')
| e_predzero :
eval (tm_pred tm_zero) tm_zero
| e_predsucc : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval (tm_pred (tm_succ t)) t
| e_pred : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval (tm_pred t) (tm_pred t')
| e_iszerozero :
eval (tm_iszero tm_zero) tm_true
| e_iszerosucc : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval (tm_iszero (tm_succ t)) tm_false
| e_iszero : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval (tm_iszero t) (tm_iszero t').
(** We define multi-step evaluation with the relation
[eval_many]. This relation includes all of the pairs of
terms that are connected by sequences of evaluation steps.
*)
Inductive eval_many : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| m_refl : forall t,
eval_many t t
| m_step : forall t t' u,
eval t t' ->
eval_many t' u ->
eval_many t u.
(** *** Exercise
Multi-step evaluation is often defined as the "reflexive,
transitive closure" of single-step evaluation. Write an
inductively defined relation [eval_rtc] that corresponds to
that verbal description.
In case you get stuck or need a hint, you can find solutions
to all the exercises near the bottom of the file.
*)
(** A term is a [normal_form] if there is no term to which it
can step. Note the concrete syntax for negation and
existential quantification in the definition below.
*)
Definition normal_form (t : tm) : Prop :=
~ exists t', eval t t'.
(** *** Exercise
Sometimes it is more convenient to use a big-step semantics
for a language. Add the remaining constructors to finish
the inductive definition [full_eval] for the big-step
semantics that corresponds to the small-step semantics
defined by [eval]. Build the inference rules so that
[full_eval t v] logically implies both [eval_many t v] and
[value v]. In order to do this, you may need to add the
premise [nvalue v] to the appropriate cases.
Hint: You should end up with a total of 8 cases.
<<
Inductive full_eval : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| f_value : forall v,
value v ->
full_eval v v
| f_iftrue : forall t1 t2 t3 v,
full_eval t1 tm_true ->
full_eval t2 v ->
full_eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) v
| f_succ : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t v ->
full_eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ v).
>>
*)
(** *** Tip
If you want to see the type of an identifier [x], you can
use the command [Check x.] If you want to see the
definition of an identifier [x], you can use the command
[Print x.]
*)
Check tm_if.
Check m_step.
Check value.
Print value.
(**************************************************************)
(** * Proofs *)
(**************************************************************)
(** A proposition and its proof are both represented as terms in
the calculus of inductive constructions, which is
syntactically very small.
Proof terms are most easily built interactively, using
tactics to manipulate a proof state. A proof state consists
of a set of goals (propositions or types for which you must
produce an inhabitant), each with a context of hypotheses
(inhabitants of propositions or types you are allowed to
use). A proof state begins initially with one goal (the
statement of the lemma you are tying to prove) and no
hypotheses. A goal can be solved, and thereby eliminated,
when it exactly matches one of hypotheses in the context. A
proof is completed when all goals are solved.
Tactics can be used for forward reasoning (which, roughly
speaking, means modifying the hypotheses of a context while
leaving the goal unchanged) or backward reasoning (replacing
the current goal with one or more new goals in simpler
contexts). Given the level of detail required in a formal
proof, it would be ridiculously impractical to complete a
proof using forward reasoning alone. However it is usually
both possible and practical to complete a proof using
backward reasoning alone. Therefore, we focus almost
exclusively on backward reasoning in this tutorial. Of
course, most people naturally a significant amount of
forward reasoning in their thinking process, so it may take
you a while to become accustomed to getting by without it.
We use the keyword [Lemma] to state a new proposition we
wish to prove. ([Theorem] and [Fact] are exact synonyms for
[Lemma].) The keyword [Proof], immediately following the
statement of the proposition, indicates the beginning of a
proof script. A proof script is a sequence of tactic
expressions, each concluding with a "[.]". Once all of the
goals are solved, we use the keyword [Qed] to record the
completed proof. If the proof is incomplete, we may tell
Coq to accept the lemma on faith by using [Admitted] instead
of [Qed].
We now proceed to introduce the specific proof tactics.
*)
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Working with Implication and Universal Quantification
- [intros]
- [apply]
- [apply with (x := ...)]
*)
(** *** Example
The tactic [intros x1 ... xn] moves antecedents and
universally quantified variables from the goal into the
context as hypotheses. The tactic [apply] is complementary
to [intros]. If the conclusion (the part following the
rightmost arrow) of a constructor, hypothesis, or lemma [e]
matches our current goal, then [apply e] will replace the
goal with a new goal for each premise/antecedent of [e]. If
[e] has no premises, then the current goal is solved. Using
[apply] allows us to build a proof tree from the bottom up.
In the following example, our proof script will effectively
build the following proof tree:
<<
nvalue t
---------------------------- (e_predsucc)
eval (tm_pred (tm_succ t)) t
------------------------------------------------ (e_succ)
eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t)
>>
Step through the proof to see how this tree is constructed.
For each tactic, we give the corresponding statement in a
written proof. (The uses of [Check] are inessential.)
*)
Lemma e_succ_pred_succ : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t).
Proof.
(** Let [t] be a [tm]. *)
intros t.
(** Assume that [t] is an [nvalue] (and let's call that
assumption [Hn] for future reference). *)
intros Hn.
(** By [e_succ], in order to prove our conclusion, it suffices
to prove that [eval (tm_pred (tm_succ t)) t]. *)
Check e_succ.
apply e_succ.
(** That, in turn, can be shown by [e_predsucc], if we are
able to show that [nvalue t]. *)
Check e_predsucc.
apply e_predsucc.
(** But, in fact, we assumed [nvalue t]. *)
apply Hn.
Qed.
(** *** Hint for PG users
If you place the cursor after [Proof.] and do C-c C-return,
you'll notice that the window displaying Coq's responses is
(annoyingly) empty, instead of showing what is to be proved.
The reason for this is that, actually, a different buffer is
being displayed! (To see this, do C-c C-n and C-c C-u a few
times and notice that the buffer name in the mode line
changes.) You can use C-c C-p to switch the display back
from the *response* buffer to the *goals* buffer.
*)
(** *** Example
Now consider, for a moment, the rule [m_step]:
<<
eval t t' eval_many t' u
------------------------- (m_step)
eval_many t u
>>
If we have a goal such as [eval_many e1 e2], we should be
able to use [apply m_step] in order to replace it with the
goals [eval e1 t'] and [eval_many t' e2]. But what exactly
is [t'] here? When and how is it chosen? It stands to
reason the conclusion is justified if we can come up with
any [t'] for which the premises can be justified.
Now we note that, in the Coq syntax for the type of
[m_step], all three variables [t], [t'], and [u] are
universally quantified. The tactic [apply m_step] will use
pattern matching between our goal and the conclusion of
[m_step] to find the only possible instantiation of [t] and
[u]. However, [apply m_step] will raise an error since it
does not know how it should instantiate [t']. In this case,
the [apply] tactic takes a [with] clause that allows us to
provide this instantiation. This is demonstrated in the
proof below. (Note that the use of this feature means that
our proof scripts are not invariant under alpha-equivalence
on the types of our constructors and lemmas. If this is a
concern, there are other means of achieving the same result
in a way that is compatible with alpha-conversion. See the
next example.)
Observe how this works in the proof script below. The proof
tree here gives a visual representation of the proof term we
are going to construct and the proof script has again been
annotated with the steps in English.
<<
Letting s = tm_succ
p = tm_pred
lem = e_succ_pred_succ,
nvalue t
- - - - - - - - - - - - (lem) --------------------- (m_refl)
eval (s (p (s t))) (s t) eval_many (s t) (s t)
--------------------------------------------------- (m_step)
eval_many (s (p (s t))) (s t)
>>
*)
Lemma m_succ_pred_succ : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval_many (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t).
Proof.
(** Let [t] be a [tm], and assume [nvalue t]. *)
intros t Hn.
(** By [m_step], to show our conclusion, it suffices to find
some [t'] for which
[eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) t']
and
[eval t' (tm_succ t)].
Let us choose [t'] to be [tm_succ t]. *)
Check m_step.
apply m_step with (t' := tm_succ t).
(** By the lemma [e_succ_pred_succ], to show
[eval (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t)],
it suffices to show [nvalue t]. *)
Check e_succ_pred_succ.
apply e_succ_pred_succ.
(** And, in fact, we assumed [nvluae t]. *)
apply Hn.
(** Moreover, by the rule [m_refl], we also may conclude
[eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ t)]. *)
Check m_refl.
apply m_refl.
Qed.
(** *** Example
Coq is built around the Curry-Howard correspondence.
Proofs of universally quantified propositions are functions
that take the witness of the quantifier as an argument.
Similarly, proofs of implications are functions that take
one proof as an argument and return another proof. Observe
the types of the following terms.
*)
Check (e_succ_pred_succ).
Check (e_succ_pred_succ tm_zero).
Check (n_zero).
Check (e_succ_pred_succ tm_zero n_zero).
(** *** Example
Any tactic like [apply] that takes the name of a constructor
or lemma as an argument can just as easily be given a more
complicated expression as an argument. Thus, we may use
function application to construct proof objects on the fly
in these cases. Observe how this technique can be used to
rewrite the proof of the previous lemma.
Although, we have eliminated one use of [apply], this is not
necessarily an improvement over the previous proof.
However, there are cases where this technique is quite
valuable.
*)
Lemma m_succ_pred_succ_alt : forall t,
nvalue t ->
eval_many (tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t))) (tm_succ t).
Proof.
intros t Hn.
Check m_step.
apply (m_step
(tm_succ (tm_pred (tm_succ t)))
(tm_succ t)
(tm_succ t)
).
Check e_succ_pred_succ.
apply (e_succ_pred_succ t Hn).
Check m_refl.
apply (m_refl (tm_succ t)).
Qed.
(** *** Hint for PG users
By default, the "." key is "electric" -- it inserts a period
_and_ causes the material up to the cursor to be sent to
Coq. If you find this behavior annoying, it can be toggled
by doing "C-c .".
*)
(*
LAB 1: (10 minutes)
Work on the following three exercises.
*)
(** *** Exercise
Write a proof script to prove the following lemma, based
upon the proof given in English.
Note: The lemma and the next should be useful in later
proofs.
*)
Lemma m_one : forall t1 t2,
eval t1 t2 ->
eval_many t1 t2.
Proof.
intros.
apply m_step with (t':= t2).
exact H.
apply m_refl.
(** Let [t1] and [t2] be terms, and assume [eval t1 t2]. We
may conclude [eval_many t1 t2] by [m_step] if we can find
a term [t'] such that [eval t1 t'] and [eval_many t' t2].
We will choose [t'] to be [t2]. Now we can show
[eval t1 t2] by our assumption, and we can show
[eval_many t2 t2] by [m_refl]. *)
(* to finish *)
Qed.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma m_two : forall t1 t2 t3,
eval t1 t2 ->
eval t2 t3 ->
eval_many t1 t3.
Proof. intros. econstructor. eauto. eauto. econstructor. eauto. auto. constructor.
Qed.
(** Let [t1], [t2], and [t3] be terms. Assume [eval t1 t2]
and [eval t2 t3]. By [m_step], we may conclude that
[eval_many t1 t3] if we can find a term [t'] such that
[eval t1 t'] and [eval_many t' t3]. Let's choose [t'] to
be [t2]. We know [eval t1 t2] holds by assumption. In
the other case, by the lemma [m_one], to show [eval_many
t2 t3], it suffices to show [eval t2 t3], which is one of
our assumptions. *)
(* to finish *)
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma m_iftrue_step : forall t t1 t2 u,
eval t tm_true ->
eval_many t1 u ->
eval_many (tm_if t t1 t2) u.
Proof. intros. econstructor. constructor. eauto. auto. econstructor. constructor. assumption.
Qed.
(** Let [t], [t1], [t2], and [u] be terms. Assume that
[eval t tm_true] and [eval_many t1 u]. To show
[eval_many (tm_if t t1 t2) u], by [m_step], it suffices to
find a [t'] for which [eval (tm_if t t1 t2) t'] and
[eval_many t' u]. Let us choose [t'] to be
[tm_if tm_true t1 t2]. Now we can use [e_if] to show that
[eval (tm_if t t1 t2) (tm_if tm_true t1 t2)] if we can
show [eval t tm_true], which is actually one of our
assumptions. Moreover, using [m_step] once more, we can
show [eval_many (tm_if tm_true t1 t2) u] where [t'] is
607
[eval (tm_if t t1 t2) (tm_if tm_true t1 t2)] if we can
608
show [eval t tm_true], which is actually one of our
609
assumptions. Moreover, using [m_step] once more, we can
610
show [eval_many (tm_if tm_true t1 t2) u] where [t'] is
611
chosen to be [t1]. Doing so leaves us to show
612
[eval (tm_if tm_true t1 t2) t1] and [eval_many t1 u]. The
613
former holds by [e_iftrue] and the latter holds by
614
assumption. *)
615
616
(* to finish *)
617
Admitted.
618
619
(**************************************************************)
620
(** ** Working with Definitions
621
- [unfold]
622
*)
623
624
(** *** Example
625
There is a notion of equivalence on Coq terms that arises
626
from the conversion rules of the underlying calculus of
627
constructions. It is sometimes useful to be able to replace
628
one term in a proof with an equivalent one. For instance,
629
we may want to replace a defined name with its definition.
630
This sort of replacement can be done the tactic [unfold].
631
This tactic can be used to manipulate the goal or the
632
hypotheses.
633
*)
634
635
Definition strongly_diverges t :=
636
forall u, eval_many t u -> ~ normal_form u.
637
t : tm
t1 : tm
t2 : tm
u : tm
H : eval t tm_true
H0 : eval_many t1 u
__________________________________________________
eval_many (tm_if tm_true t1 t2) u
1 subgoal
Current cost: 4
chosen to be [t1]. Doing so leaves us to show
[eval (tm_if tm_true t1 t2) t1] and [eval_many t1 u]. The
former holds by [e_iftrue] and the latter holds by
assumption. *)
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Working with Definitions
- [unfold]
*)
(** *** Example
There is a notion of equivalence on Coq terms that arises
from the conversion rules of the underlying calculus of
constructions. It is sometimes useful to be able to replace
one term in a proof with an equivalent one. For instance,
we may want to replace a defined name with its definition.
This sort of replacement can be done the tactic [unfold].
This tactic can be used to manipulate the goal or the
hypotheses.
*)
Definition strongly_diverges t :=
forall u, eval_many t u -> ~ normal_form u.
Lemma unfold_example : forall t t',
strongly_diverges t ->
eval t t' ->
strongly_diverges t'.
Proof.
intros t t' Hd He.
unfold strongly_diverges. intros u Hm.
unfold strongly_diverges in Hd.
apply Hd. apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He.
apply Hm.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise
In reality, many tactics will perform conversion
automatically as necessary. Try removing the uses of
[unfold] from the above proof to check which ones were
necessary.
*)
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Working with Conjunction and Disjunction
- [split]
- [left]
- [right]
- [destruct] (for conjunction and disjunction)
*)
(** *** Example
If [H] is the name of a conjunctive hypothesis, then
[destruct H as p] will replace the hypothesis [H] with its
components using the names in the pattern [p]. Observe the
pattern in the example below.
*)
Lemma m_two_conj : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' /\ eval t' t'' ->
eval_many t t''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' H.
destruct H as [ He1 He2 ].
apply m_two with (t2 := t').
apply He1.
apply He2.
Qed.
(** *** Example
Patterns may be nested to break apart nested structures.
Note that infix conjunction is right-associative, which is
significant when trying to write nested patterns. We will
later see how to use [destruct] on many different sorts of
hypotheses.
*)
Lemma m_three_conj : forall t t' t'' t''',
eval t t' /\ eval t' t'' /\ eval t'' t''' ->
eval_many t t'''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' t''' H.
destruct H as [ He1 [ He2 He3 ] ].
apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He1.
apply m_two with (t2 := t'').
apply He2.
apply He3.
Qed.
(** *** Example
If your goal is a conjunction, use [split] to break it apart
into two separate subgoals.
*)
Lemma m_three : forall t t' t'' t''',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
eval t'' t''' ->
eval_many t t'''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' t''' He1 He2 He3.
apply m_three_conj with (t' := t') (t'' := t'').
split.
apply He1.
split.
apply He2.
apply He3.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise
Hint: You might find lemma [m_three] useful here.
*)
Lemma m_if_iszero_conj : forall v t2 t2' t3 t3',
nvalue v /\ eval t2 t2' /\ eval t3 t3' ->
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero tm_zero) t2 t3) t2' /\
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero (tm_succ v)) t2 t3) t3'.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Example
If the goal is a disjunction, we can use the [left] or
[right] tactics to solve it by proving the left or right
side of the conclusion.
*)
Lemma true_and_succ_zero_values :
value tm_true /\ value (tm_succ tm_zero).
Proof.
unfold value. split.
left. apply b_true.
right. apply n_succ. apply n_zero.
Qed.
(** *** Example
If we have a disjunction in the context, we can use
[destruct] to reason by cases on the hypothesis. Note the
syntax of the associated pattern.
*)
Lemma e_if_true_or_false : forall t1 t2,
eval t1 tm_true \/ eval t1 tm_false ->
eval_many (tm_if t1 t2 t2) t2.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 H. destruct H as [ He1 | He2 ].
apply m_two with (t2 := tm_if tm_true t2 t2).
apply e_if. apply He1.
apply e_iftrue.
apply m_two with (t2 := tm_if tm_false t2 t2).
apply e_if. apply He2.
apply e_iffalse.
Qed.
(*
LAB 2: (10 minutes)
Work on the following exercise.
*)
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma two_values : forall t u,
value t /\ value u ->
bvalue t \/
bvalue u \/
(nvalue t /\ nvalue u).
Proof.
(** We know [value t] and [value u], which means either
[bvalue t] or [nvalue t], and either [bvalue u] or
[nvalue u]. Consider the case in which
[bvalue t] holds. Then one of the disjuncts of our
conclusion is proved. Next, consider the case in which
[nvalue t] holds. Now consider the subcase where
[bvalue u] holds. ... *)
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Example
[destruct] can be used on propositions with implications.
This will have the effect of performing [destruct] on the
conclusion of the implication, while leaving the hypotheses
of the implication as additional subgoals.
*)
Lemma destruct_example : forall bv t t' t'',
bvalue bv ->
(value bv -> eval t t' /\ eval t' t'') ->
eval_many t t''.
Proof.
intros bv t t' t'' Hbv H. destruct H as [ H1 H2 ].
Show 2.
unfold value. left. apply Hbv.
apply m_two with (t2 := t').
apply H1.
apply H2.
Qed.
(** *** Tip
After applying a tactic that introduces multiple subgoals,
it is sometimes useful to see not only the subgoals
themselves but also their hypotheses. Adding the command
[Show n.] to your proof script to cause Coq to display the
nth subgoal in full.
*)
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Reasoning by Cases and Induction
- [destruct] (for inductively defined propositions)
- [induction]
*)
(** *** Example
Use [destruct] to reason by cases on an inductively defined
datatype or proposition.
Note: It is possible to supply [destruct] with a pattern in
these instances also. However, the patterns become
increasingly complex for bigger inductive definitions; so it
is often more practical to omit the pattern (thereby letting
Coq choose the names of the terms and hypotheses in each
case), in spite of the fact that this adds an element of
fragility to the proof script (since the proof script will
mention names that were system-generated).
*)
Lemma e_iszero_nvalue : forall v,
nvalue v ->
eval (tm_iszero v) tm_true \/
eval (tm_iszero v) tm_false.
Proof.
intros v Hn. destruct Hn.
(* Case [n_zero].
Note how [v] becomes [tm_zero] in the goal. *)
left. apply e_iszerozero.
(* Case [n_succ].
Note how [v] becomes [tm_succ v] in the goal. *)
right. apply e_iszerosucc. apply Hn.
Qed.
(** *** Example
You can use [induction] to reason by induction on an
inductively defined datatype or proposition. This is the
same as [destruct], except that it also introduces an
induction hypothesis in the inductive cases.
*)
Lemma m_iszero : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_iszero t) (tm_iszero u).
Proof.
intros t u Hm. induction Hm.
apply m_refl.
apply m_step with (t' := tm_iszero t').
apply e_iszero. apply H.
apply IHHm.
Qed.
(*
LAB 3: (5 minutes)
Work on the following exercise.
*)
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma m_trans : forall t t' u,
eval_many t t' ->
eval_many t' u ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
(** We proceed by induction on the derivation of
[eval_many t t'].
Case [m_refl]: Since [t] and [t'] must be the same, our
conclusion holds by assumption.
Case [m_step]: Now let's rename the [t'] from the lemma
statement to [u0] (as Coq likely will) and observe that
there must be some [t'] (from above the line of the
[m_step] rule) such that [eval t t'] and
[eval_many t' u0]. Our conclusion follows from from
an application of [m_step] with our new [t'] and our
induction hypothesis, which allows us to piece together
[eval_many t' u0] and [eval_many u0 u] to get
[eval_many t' u]. *)
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Exercise
It is possible to use [destruct] not just on hypotheses but
on any lemma we have proved. If we have a lemma
<<
lemma1 : P /\ Q
>>
then we can use the tactic
<<
destruct lemma1 as [ H1 H2 ].
>>
to continue our proof with [H1 : P] and [H2 : Q] in our
context. This works even if the lemma has antecedents (they
become new subgoals); however it fail if the lemma has a
universal quantifier, such as this:
<<
lemma2 : forall x, P(x) /\ Q(x)
>>
However, remember that we can build a proof of
[P(e) /\ Q(e)] (which can be destructed) using the Coq
expression [lemma2 e]. So we need to phrase our tactic as
<<
destruct (lemma2 e) as [ H1 H2 ].
>>
An example of this technique is below.
*)
Lemma m_iszero_nvalue : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
eval_many t v ->
eval_many (tm_iszero t) tm_true \/
eval_many (tm_iszero t) tm_false.
Proof.
intros t v Hnv Hm.
destruct (e_iszero_nvalue v) as [ H1 | H2 ].
apply Hnv.
left. apply m_trans with (t' := tm_iszero v).
apply m_iszero. apply Hm.
apply m_one. apply H1.
right. apply m_trans with (t' := tm_iszero v).
apply m_iszero. apply Hm.
apply m_one. apply H2.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise
Prove the following lemma.
Hint: You may be interested in some previously proved
lemmas, such as [m_one] and [m_trans].
Note: Even though this lemma is in a comment, its solution
is also at the bottom. (Coq will give an error if we leave
it uncommented since it mentions the [eval_rtc] relation,
which was the solution to another exercise.)
<<
Lemma eval_rtc_many : forall t u,
eval_rtc t u ->
eval_many t u.
>>
*)
(** *** Exercise
Prove the following lemma.
<<
Lemma eval_many_rtc : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_rtc t u.
>>
*)
(** *** Exercise
Prove the following lemma.
<<
Lemma full_eval_to_value : forall t v,
full_eval t v ->
value v.
>>
*)
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Working with Existential Quantification
- [exists]
- [destruct] (for existential propositions)
*)
(** *** Example
Use [exists] to give the witness for an existential
quantifier in your goal.
*)
Lemma if_bvalue : forall t1 t2 t3,
bvalue t1 ->
exists u, eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) u.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 t3 Hb. destruct Hb.
exists t2. apply e_iftrue.
exists t3. apply e_iffalse.
Qed.
(** *** Example
You may use [destruct] to break open an existential
hypothesis.
*)
Lemma m_two_exists : forall t u,
(exists w, eval t w /\ eval w u) ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
intros t u H.
destruct H as [ w He ].
destruct He as [ He1 He2 ].
apply m_two with (t2 := w).
apply He1.
apply He2.
Qed.
(** *** Example
Tip: We can combine patterns that destruct existentials with
patterns that destruct other logical connectives.
Here is the same proof with just one use of [destruct].
*)
Lemma m_two_exists' : forall t u,
(exists w, eval t w /\ eval w u) ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
intros t u H. destruct H as [ w [ He1 He2 ] ].
apply m_two with (t2 := w).
apply He1.
apply He2.
Qed.
(** *** Example
Tip: We give patterns to the [intros] tactic to destruct
hypotheses as we introduce them.
Here is the same proof again without any uses of [destruct].
*)
Lemma m_two_exists'' : forall t u,
(exists w, eval t w /\ eval w u) ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
intros t u [ w [ He1 He2 ] ].
apply m_two with (t2 := w).
apply He1.
apply He2.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma value_can_expand : forall v,
value v ->
exists u, eval u v.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(*
LAB 4: (10 minutes)
Work on the following exercise.
*)
(** *** Exercise
Tip: You should find the lemma [m_iszero] useful. Use
[Check m_iszero.] if you've forgotten its statement.
*)
Lemma exists_iszero_nvalue : forall t,
(exists nv, nvalue nv /\ eval_many t nv) ->
exists bv, eval_many (tm_iszero t) bv.
Proof.
(** There exists some [nv] such that [nvalue nv]. Consider
the case where [nv] is [tm_zero]. Then choose [bv] to
be [tm_true]. By [m_trans], we can show that
[eval_many (tm_iszero t) tm_true] by showing
[eval_many (tm_iszero t) (tm_iszero tm_zero)] and
[eval_many (tm_iszero tm_zero) tm_true]. The former
follows from [m_iszero] and our assumption. The latter
follows from [m_one] and the rule [e_iszerozero]. On the
other hand, in the case where [nv] is built from
[tm_succ], we choose [bv] to be [tm_false] and the proof
follows similarly. *)
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Working with Negation
- [unfold not]
- [destruct] (for negation)
*)
(** *** Example
The standard library defines an uninhabited type [False] and
defines [not P] to stand for [P -> False]. Furthermore, Coq
defines the notation [~ P] to stand for [not P]. (Such
notations only affect parsing and printing -- Coq views [not
P] and [~ P] as being syntactically equal.)
The most basic way to work with negated statements is to
unfold [not] and treat [False] just as any other
proposition.
(Note how multiple definitions can be unfolded with one use
of [unfold]. Also, as noted earlier, many uses of [unfold]
are not strictly necessary. You can try deleting the uses
from the proof below to check that the proof script still
works.)
*)
Lemma normal_form_succ : forall t,
normal_form (tm_succ t) ->
normal_form t.
Proof.
intros t Hnf.
unfold normal_form. unfold not.
unfold normal_form, not in Hnf.
intros [ t' H' ]. apply Hnf.
exists (tm_succ t'). apply e_succ. apply H'.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma normal_form_to_forall : forall t,
normal_form t ->
forall u, ~ eval t u.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma normal_form_from_forall : forall t,
(forall u, ~ eval t u) ->
normal_form t.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Example
If you happen to have [False] as a hypothesis, you may use
[destruct] on that hypothesis to solve your goal.
*)
Lemma False_hypothesis : forall v,
False ->
value v.
Proof.
intros v H. destruct H.
Qed.
(** *** Example
Recalling that [destruct] can be used on propositions with
antecedents and that negation is simply an abbreviation for
an implication, using [destruct] on a negated hypothesis has
the derived behavior of replacing our goal with the
proposition that was negated in our context.
Tip: We actually don't even need to do the unfolding below
because [destruct] would have done it for us.
*)
Lemma destruct_negation_example : forall t v,
value v ->
eval t tm_zero ->
(value v -> normal_form t) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
intros t v Hnv He Hnf.
unfold normal_form, not in Hnf.
(* As usual, unfolding was optional here. *)
destruct Hnf.
apply Hnv.
exists tm_zero. apply He.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise
This one may be a bit tricky. Start by using [destruct] on
one of your hypotheses.
*)
Lemma negation_exercise : forall v1 v2,
~ (value v1 \/ value v2) ->
~ (~ bvalue v1 /\ ~ bvalue v2) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Working with Equality
- [reflexivity]
- [subst]
- [rewrite]
- [inversion] (on equalities)
*)
(** *** Example
If you have an equality in your context, there are several
ways to substitute one side of the equality for the other in
your goal or in other hypotheses.
If one side of the equality is a variable [x], then the
tactic [subst x] will replace all occurrences of [x] in the
context and goal with the other side of the quality and will
remove [x] from your context.
Use [reflexivity] to solve a goal of the form [e = e].
*)
Lemma equality_example_1 : forall t1 t2 t3 u1 u2,
t1 = tm_iszero u1 ->
t2 = tm_succ u2 ->
t3 = tm_succ t2 ->
tm_if t1 t2 t3 =
tm_if (tm_iszero u1) (tm_succ u2) (tm_succ (tm_succ u2)).
Proof.
intros t1 t2 t3 u1 u2 Heq1 Heq2 Heq3.
subst t1. subst t2. subst t3. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** *** Example
If neither side of the equality in your context is a
variable (or if you don't want to discard the hypothesis),
you can use the [rewrite] tactic to perform a substitution.
The arrow after [rewrite] indicates the direction of the
substitution. As demonstrated, you may perform rewriting in
the goal or in a hypothesis.
*)
Lemma equality_example_2a : forall t u v,
tm_succ t = tm_succ u ->
eval (tm_succ u) v ->
eval (tm_succ t) v.
Proof.
intros t u v Heq He. rewrite -> Heq. apply He.
Qed.
Lemma equality_example_2b : forall t u v,
tm_succ t = tm_succ u ->
eval (tm_succ u) v ->
eval (tm_succ t) v.
Proof.
intros t u v Heq He. rewrite <- Heq in He. apply He.
Qed.
(** *** Example
We also note that, analogously with [destruct], we may use
[rewrite] even with a hypothesis (or lemma) that has
antecedents.
*)
Lemma equality_example_2c : forall t u v,
nvalue v ->
(nvalue v -> tm_succ t = tm_succ u) ->
eval (tm_succ u) v ->
eval (tm_succ t) v.
Proof.
intros t u v Hnv Heq He. rewrite <- Heq in He.
apply He.
apply Hnv.
Qed.
(** *** Example
If you need to derive additional equalities implied by an
equality in your context (e.g., by the principle of
constructor injectivity), you may use [inversion].
[inversion] is a powerful tactic that uses unification to
introduce more equalities into your context. (You will
observe that it also performs some substitutions in your
goal.)
*)
Lemma equality_example_3 : forall t u,
tm_succ t = tm_succ u ->
t = u.
Proof.
intros t u Heq. inversion Heq. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma equality_exercise : forall t1 t2 t3 u1 u2 u3 u4,
tm_if t1 t2 t3 = tm_if u1 u2 u2 ->
tm_if t1 t2 t3 = tm_if u3 u3 u4 ->
t1 = u4.
Proof.
intros.
inversion H as [ (Ht1u1, Ht2u2, Ht3u2)].
rewrite Ht1u1 in H0.
rewrite Ht2u2 in H0.
rewrite Ht3u2 in H0.
inversion H0.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** *** Example
[inversion] will also solve a goal when unification fails on
a hypothesis. (Internally, Coq can construct a proof of
[False] from contradictory equalities.)
*)
Lemma equality_example_4 :
tm_zero = tm_true ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
Qed.
(*
LAB 5: (10 minutes)
Work on [equality_exercise] above and [succ_not_circular]
below.
*)
(** *** Exercise
Note: [e1 <> e2] is a notation for [~ e1 = e2], i.e., the
two are treated as syntactically equal.
Note: This is fairly trivial to prove if we have a size
function on terms and some automation. With just the tools
we have described so far, it requires just a little bit of
work.
Hint: The proof requires induction on [t]. (This is the
first example of induction on datatypes, but it is even more
straightforward than induction on propositions.) In each
case, unfold the negation, pull the equality into the
context, and use [inversion] to eliminate contradictory
equalities.
*)
Lemma succ_not_circular : forall t,
t <> tm_succ t.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Reasoning by Inversion
- [inversion] (on propositions)
*)
(** *** Example
The [inversion] tactic also allows you to reason by
inversion on an inductively defined proposition as in paper
proofs: we try to match some proposition with the conclusion
of each inference rule and only consider the cases (possibly
none) where there is a successful unification. In those
cases, we may use the premises of the inference rule in our
reasoning.
Since [inversion] may generate many equalities between
variables, it is useful to know that using [subst] without
an argument will perform all possible substitutions for
variables. It is a little difficult to predict which
variables will be eliminated and which will be kept by this
tactic, but this is a typical sort of trade-off when using
powerful tactics.
(The use of [subst] in this proof is superfluous, but you
can observe that it simplifies the context.)
*)
Lemma value_succ_nvalue : forall t,
value (tm_succ t) ->
nvalue t.
Proof.
intros t H. unfold value in H. destruct H as [ H1 | H2 ].
(* No unification is possible -- [inversion] solves goal. *)
inversion H1.
(* Just the [n_succ] cases unifies with H2. *)
inversion H2. subst. apply H0.
Qed.
(*
LAB 6: (10 minutes)
Work on the exercise below.
*)
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma inversion_exercise : forall t,
normal_form t ->
eval_many (tm_pred t) tm_zero ->
nvalue t.
Proof.
(** By inversion on the [eval_many] relation, then conclusion
[eval_many (tm_pred t) tm_zero] must have been derived by
the rule [m_step], which means there is some [t'] for
which [eval (tm_pred t) t'] and [eval_many t' tm_zero].
Now, by inversion on the [eval] relation, there are only
three ways that [eval (tm_pred t) t'] could have been
derived:
* By [e_predzero], with [t] and [t'] both being equal to
[tm_zero]. Our conclusion follows from [n_zero].
* By [e_predsucc], with [t] being [tm_succ t0] where we
have [nvalue t0]. In this case, our conclusion is
provable with [n_succ].
* By [e_pred], with [t] taking an evaluation step. This
contradicts our assumption that [t] is a normal form
(which can be shown by using [destruct] on that
assumption). *)
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Exercise
Tip: Nested patterns will be useful here.
*)
Lemma contradictory_equalities_exercise :
(exists t, exists u, exists v,
value t /\
t = tm_succ u /\
u = tm_pred v) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma eval_fact_exercise : forall t1 t2,
eval (tm_iszero (tm_pred t1)) t2 ->
eval t2 tm_false ->
exists u, t1 = tm_succ u.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma normal_form_if : forall t1 t2 t3,
normal_form (tm_if t1 t2 t3) ->
t1 <> tm_true /\ t1 <> tm_false /\ normal_form t1.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Additional Important Tactics
- [generalize dependent]
- [assert]
- [;]
- [clear]
*)
(** *** Example
Sometimes we need to have a tactic that moves hypotheses
from our context back into our goal. Often this is
because we want to perform induction in the middle of a
proof and will not get a sufficiently general induction
hypothesis without a goal of the correct form. (To be
specific, if we need to have an induction hypothesis with a
[forall] quantifier in front, then we must make sure our
goal has a [forall] quantifier in front at the time we
invoke the [induction] tactic.) Observe how [generalize
dependent] achieves this in the proof below, moving the
variable [t] and all dependent hypotheses back into the
goal. You may want to remove the use of [generalize
dependent] to convince yourself that it is performing an
essential role here.
*)
Lemma value_is_normal_form : forall v,
value v ->
normal_form v.
Proof.
intros v [ Hb | Hn ] [ t He ].
destruct Hb.
inversion He.
inversion He.
generalize dependent t. induction Hn.
intros t He. inversion He.
intros u He. inversion He. subst. destruct (IHHn t').
apply H0.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise
Coq has many operations (called "tacticals") to combine
smaller tactics into larger ones.
If [t1] and [t2] are tactics, then [t1; t2] is a tactic that
executes [t1], and then executes [t2] on subgoals left by or
newly generated by [t1]. This can help to eliminate
repetitious use of tactics. Two idiomatic uses are
performing [subst] after [inversion] and performing [intros]
after [induction]. More opportunities to use this tactical
can usually be discovered after writing a proof. (It is
worth noting that some uses of this tactical can make proofs
less readable or more difficult to maintain. Alternatively,
some uses can make proofs more readable or easier to
maintain. It is always good to think about your priorities
when writing a proof script.)
Revise the proof for [value_is_normal_form] to include uses
of the [;] tactical.
*)
(** *** Example
Sometimes it is helpful to be able to use forward reasoning
in a proof. One form of forward reasoning can be done with
the tactic [assert]. [assert] adds a new hypothesis to the
context but asks us to first justify it.
*)
Lemma nvalue_is_normal_form : forall v,
nvalue v ->
normal_form v.
Proof.
intros v Hnv.
assert (value v) as Hv. right. apply Hnv.
apply value_is_normal_form. apply Hv.
Qed.
(** *** Example
[assert] can also be supplied with a tactic that proves the
assertion. We rewrite the above proof using this form.
*)
Lemma nvalue_is_normal_form' : forall v,
nvalue v ->
normal_form v.
Proof.
intros v Hnv.
assert (value v) as Hv by (right; apply Hnv).
apply value_is_normal_form. apply Hv.
Qed.
(** *** Example
The proof below introduces two new, simple tactics. First,
the tactic [replace e1 with e2] performs a substitution in
the goal and then requires that you prove [e2 = e1] as a new
subgoal. This often allows us to avoid more cumbersome
forms of forward reasoning. Second, the [clear] tactic
discards a hypothesis from the context. Of course, this
tactic is never needed, but it can be nice to use when there
are complicated, irrelevant hypotheses in the context.
*)
Lemma single_step_to_multi_step_determinacy :
(forall t u1 u2, eval t u1 -> eval t u2 -> u1 = u2) ->
forall t v1 v2,
eval_many t v1 -> normal_form v1 ->
eval_many t v2 -> normal_form v2 ->
v1 = v2.
Proof.
intros H t v1 v2 Hm1 Hnf1 Hm2 Hnf2. induction Hm1.
clear H. destruct Hm2.
reflexivity.
destruct Hnf1. exists t'. apply H.
destruct Hm2.
destruct Hnf2. exists t'. apply H0.
apply IHHm1; clear IHHm1.
apply Hnf1.
replace t' with t'0.
apply Hm2.
apply H with (t := t).
apply H1.
apply H0.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise
This proof is lengthy and thus somewhat challenging. All of
the techniques from this section will be useful; some will
be essential. In particular, you will need to use
[generalize dependent] at the beginning of the proof. You
will find [assert] helpful in the cases where your
assumptions are contradictory but none of them are in a
negative form. In that situation, you can assert a negative
statement that follows from your hypotheses (recall that
[normal_form] is a negative statement). Finally, you will
want to use the above lemma [nvalue_is_normal_form]. Good
luck!
*)
Theorem eval_deterministic : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t t'' ->
t' = t''.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Exercise
Prove the following lemmas. The last is quite long, and you
may wish to wait until you know more about automation.
<<
Lemma full_eval_from_value : forall v w,
value v ->
full_eval v w ->
v = w.
Lemma eval_full_eval : forall t t' v,
eval t t' ->
full_eval t' v ->
full_eval t v.
Lemma full_eval_complete : forall t v,
value v ->
eval_many t v ->
full_eval t v.
>>
*)
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Basic Automation
- [eapply], [esplit]
- [auto], [eauto]
*)
(** *** Example
You can use [eapply e] instead of [apply e with (x := e1)].
This will generate subgoals containing unification variables
that will get unified during subsequent uses of [apply].
*)
Lemma m_if : forall t1 u1 t2 t3,
eval_many t1 u1 ->
eval_many (tm_if t1 t2 t3) (tm_if u1 t2 t3).
Proof.
intros t1 u1 t2 t3 Hm. induction Hm.
apply m_refl.
eapply m_step.
apply e_if. apply H.
apply IHHm.
Qed.
(** *** Example
You can use [esplit] to turn an existentially quantified
variable in your goal into a unification variable.
*)
Lemma exists_pred_zero :
exists u, eval (tm_pred tm_zero) u.
Proof.
esplit. apply e_predzero.
Qed.
(** *** Example
The [auto] tactic solves goals that are solvable by any
combination of
- [intros]
- [apply] (used on some local hypothesis)
- [split], [left], [right]
- [reflexivity]
If [auto] cannot solve the goal, it will leave the proof
state completely unchanged (without generating any errors).
The lemma below is a proposition that has been contrived for
the sake of demonstrating the scope of the [auto] tactic and
does not say anything of practical interest. So instead of
thinking about what it means, you should think about the
operations that [auto] had to perform to solve the goal.
Note: It is important to remember that [auto] does not
destruct hypotheses! There are more advanced forms of
automation available that do destruct hypotheses in some
specific ways.
*)
Lemma auto_example : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
(forall u, eval t t' -> eval t' u -> eval_many t u) ->
eval t' t \/ t = t /\ eval_many t t''.
Proof.
auto.
Qed.
(** *** Example
The [eauto] tactic solves goals that are solvable by some
combination of
- [intros]
- [eapply] (used on some local hypothesis)
- [split], [left], [right]
- [esplit]
- [reflexivity]
This lemma has two significantly differences from the
previous one, both of which render [auto] useless.
*)
Lemma eauto_example : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
(forall u, eval t u -> eval u t'' -> eval_many t t'') ->
eval t' t \/ (exists u, t = u) /\ eval_many t t''.
Proof.
eauto.
Qed.
(** *** Example
You can enhance [auto] (or [eauto]) by appending [using x_1,
..., x_n], where each [x_i] is the name of some constructor
or lemma. Then [auto] will attempt to apply those
constructors or lemmas in addition to the assumptions in
the local context.
*)
Lemma eauto_using_example : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
eval t' t \/ t = t /\ eval_many t t''.
Proof.
eauto using m_step, m_one.
Qed.
(*
LAB 7: (5 minutes)
Work on the following exercise.
*)
(** *** Exercise
Go back and rewrite your proofs for [m_one], [m_two], and
[m_iftrue_step]. You should be able to make them very
succinct given what you know now.
*)
(** *** Exercise
See how short you can make these proofs.
Note: This is an exercise. We are not making the claim that
shorter proofs are necessarily better!
Hint: Remember that we can connect tactics in sequence with
[;]. However, as you can imagine, figuring out the best
thing to write after a [;] usually involves some trial and
error.
*)
Lemma pred_not_circular : forall t,
t <> tm_pred t.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
Lemma m_succ : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_succ t) (tm_succ u).
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
Lemma m_pred : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_pred t) (tm_pred u).
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Exercise
Go back and rewrite your proofs for [m_trans] and
[two_values]. Pulling together several tricks you've
learned, you should be able to prove [two_values] in one
(short) line.
*)
(** *** Note
Sometimes there are lemmas or constructors that are so
frequently needed by [auto] that we don't want to have to
add them to our [using] clause each time. Coq allows us to
request that certain propositions that always be
considered by [auto] and [eauto].
The following command adds four lemmas to the default search
procedure of [auto].
*)
Hint Resolve m_if m_succ m_pred m_iszero.
(** Constructors of inductively defined propositions are some of
the most frequently needed by [auto]. Instead of writing
<<
Hint Resolve b_true b_false.
>>
we may simply write
<<
Hint Constructors bvalue.
>>
Let's add all our constructors to [auto].
*)
Hint Constructors bvalue nvalue eval eval_many.
(** By default [auto] will never try to unfold definitions to
see if a lemma or constructor can be applied. With the
[Hint Unfold] command, we can instruct [auto] to try unfold
definitions in the goal as it is working.
*)
Hint Unfold value normal_form.
(** There are a few more variants on the [Hint] command that can
be used to further customize [auto]. You can learn about
them in the Coq reference manual.
*)
(**************************************************************)
(** ** Functions and Conversion
- [Fixpoint/struct]
- [match ... end]
- [if ... then ... else ...]
- [simpl]
- [remember]
In this section we start to use Coq as a programming
language and learn how to reason about programs defined
within Coq.
*)
(** *** Example
Coq defines many datatypes in its standard libraries. Have
a quick look now through the library [Datatypes] to see some
of the basic ones, in particular [bool] and [nat]. (Note
that constructors of the datatype [nat] are the letter [O]
and the letter [S]. However, Coq will parse and print
[nat]s using a standard decimal representation.)
We define two more datatypes here that will be useful later.
*)
Inductive bool_option : Set :=
| some_bool : bool -> bool_option
| no_bool : bool_option.
Inductive nat_option : Set :=
| some_nat : nat -> nat_option
| no_nat : nat_option.
(** *** Example
We can define simple (non-recursive) functions from one
datatype to another using the [Definition] keyword. The
[match] construct allows us to do case analysis on a
datatype. The [match] expression has a first-match
semantics and allows nested patterns; however, Coq's type
checker demands that pattern-matching be exhaustive.
We define functions below for converting between Coq [bool]s
and boolean values in our object language.
*)
Definition tm_to_bool (t : tm) : bool_option :=
match t with
| tm_true => some_bool true
| tm_false => some_bool false
| _ => no_bool
end.
Definition bool_to_tm (b : bool) : tm :=
match b with
| true => tm_true
| false => tm_false
end.
(** *** Example
Coq also has an [if/then/else] expression. It can be used,
not just with the type [bool] but, in fact, with any
datatype having exactly two constructors (the first
constructor corresponding to the [then] branch and the
second to the [else] branch). Thus, we can define a
function [is_bool] as below.
*)
Definition is_bool (t : tm) : bool :=
if tm_to_bool t then true else false.
(** *** Example
To define a recursive function, use [Fixpoint] instead of
[Definition].
The type system will only allow us to write functions that
terminate. The annotation [{struct t}] here informs the
type-checker that termination is guaranteed because the
function is being defined by structural recursion on [t].
*)
Fixpoint tm_to_nat (t : tm) {struct t} : nat_option :=
match t with
| tm_zero => some_nat O
| tm_succ t1 =>
match tm_to_nat t1 with
| some_nat n => some_nat (S n)
| no_nat => no_nat
end
| _ => no_nat
end.
Fixpoint nat_to_tm (n : nat) {struct n} : tm :=
match n with
| O => tm_zero
| S m => tm_succ (nat_to_tm m)
end.
(** *** Exercise
Write a function [interp : tm -> tm] that returns the
normal form of its argument according to the small-step
semantics given by [eval].
Hint: You will want to use [tm_to_nat] (or another auxiliary
function) to prevent stuck terms from stepping in the cases
[e_predsucc] and [e_iszerosucc].
*)
(** *** Example
The tactic [simpl] (recursively) reduces the application of
a function defined by pattern-matching to an argument with a
constructor at its head. You can supply [simpl] with a
particular expression if you want to prevent it from
simplifying elsewhere.
*)
Lemma bool_tm_bool : forall b,
tm_to_bool (bool_to_tm b) = some_bool b.
Proof.
intros b. destruct b.
simpl (bool_to_tm true). simpl. reflexivity.
(* It turns out that [simpl] is unnecessary above, since
[reflexivity] can automatically check that two terms are
convertible. *)
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** *** Example
We can also apply the tactic [simpl] in our hypotheses.
*)
Lemma tm_bool_tm :forall t b,
tm_to_bool t = some_bool b ->
bool_to_tm b = t.
Proof.
intros t b Heq. destruct t.
simpl in Heq. inversion Heq.
simpl. reflexivity.
(* As with [reflexivity], [inversion] can automatically
perform reduction on terms as necessary, so the above use
of [simpl] was optional. *)
inversion Heq. reflexivity.
simpl in Heq. inversion Heq.
(* Again, the above use of [simpl] was optional. *)
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma tm_to_bool_dom_includes_bvalue : forall bv,
bvalue bv -> exists b, tm_to_bool bv = some_bool b.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma tm_to_bool_dom_only_bvalue : forall bv b,
tm_to_bool bv = some_bool b -> bvalue bv.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Example
Not all uses of [simpl] are optional. Sometimes they are
necessary so that we can use the [rewrite] tactic. Observe,
also, how using [rewrite] can automatically trigger a
reduction if it creates a redex.
*)
Lemma nat_tm_nat : forall n,
tm_to_nat (nat_to_tm n) = some_nat n.
Proof.
intros n. induction n.
reflexivity.
simpl. rewrite -> IHn. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** *** Example
Here's an example where it is necessary to use [simpl] on a
hypothesis. To trigger a reduction of a [match] expression
in a hypothesis, we use the [destruct] tactic on the
expression being matched.
*)
Lemma tm_nat_tm : forall t n,
tm_to_nat t = some_nat n ->
nat_to_tm n = t.
Proof.
intros t. induction t; intros n Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq. reflexivity.
simpl in Heq. destruct (tm_to_nat t).
inversion Heq. simpl. rewrite -> IHt.
(* Note how we may use [rewrite] even on an equation
that is preceded by some other hypotheses. *)
reflexivity.
reflexivity.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma tm_to_nat_dom_includes_nvalue : forall v,
nvalue v -> exists n, tm_to_nat v = some_nat n.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Exercise *)
Lemma tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue : forall v n,
tm_to_nat v = some_nat n -> nvalue v.
Proof.
(* to finish *)
Admitted.
(** *** Example
Using the tactic [destruct] (or [induction]) on a complex
expression (i.e., one that is not simply a variable) may not
leave you with enough information for you to finish the
proof. The tactic [remember] can help in these cases. Its
usage is demonstrated below. If you are curious, try to
finish the proof without [remember] to see what goes wrong.
*)
Lemma remember_example : forall v,
eval_many
(tm_pred (tm_succ v))
(match tm_to_nat v with
| some_nat _ => v
| no_nat => tm_pred (tm_succ v)
end).
Proof.
intros v. remember (tm_to_nat v) as x. destruct x.
apply m_one. apply e_predsucc.
eapply tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue.
rewrite <- Heqx. reflexivity.
apply m_refl.
Qed.
(** *** Exercise
Prove the following lemmas involving the function [interp]
from a previous exercise:
<<
Lemma interp_reduces : forall t,
eval_many t (interp t).
Lemma interp_fully_reduces : forall t,
normal_form (interp t).
>>
*)
(**************************************************************)
(** * Solutions to Exercises *)
(**************************************************************)
Inductive eval_rtc : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| r_eval : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval_rtc t t'
| r_refl : forall t,
eval_rtc t t
| r_trans : forall t u v,
eval_rtc t u ->
eval_rtc u v ->
eval_rtc t v.
Inductive full_eval : tm -> tm -> Prop :=
| f_value : forall v,
value v ->
full_eval v v
| f_iftrue : forall t1 t2 t3 v,
full_eval t1 tm_true ->
full_eval t2 v ->
full_eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) v
| f_iffalse : forall t1 t2 t3 v,
full_eval t1 tm_false ->
full_eval t3 v ->
full_eval (tm_if t1 t2 t3) v
| f_succ : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t v ->
full_eval (tm_succ t) (tm_succ v)
| f_predzero : forall t,
full_eval t tm_zero ->
full_eval (tm_pred t) tm_zero
| f_predsucc : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t (tm_succ v) ->
full_eval (tm_pred t) v
| f_iszerozero : forall t,
full_eval t tm_zero ->
full_eval (tm_iszero t) tm_true
| f_iszerosucc : forall t v,
nvalue v ->
full_eval t (tm_succ v) ->
full_eval (tm_iszero t) tm_false.
Lemma m_one_sol : forall t t',
eval t t' ->
eval_many t t'.
Proof.
intros t t' He. apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He.
apply m_refl.
Qed.
Lemma m_two_sol : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t' t'' ->
eval_many t t''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' He1 He2. apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply He1.
apply m_one. apply He2.
Qed.
Lemma m_iftrue_step_sol : forall t t1 t2 u,
eval t tm_true ->
eval_many t1 u ->
eval_many (tm_if t t1 t2) u.
Proof.
intros t t1 t2 u He Hm.
apply m_step with (t' := tm_if tm_true t1 t2).
apply e_if. apply He.
apply m_step with (t' := t1).
apply e_iftrue.
apply Hm.
Qed.
Lemma m_if_iszero_conj_sol : forall v t2 t2' t3 t3',
nvalue v /\ eval t2 t2' /\ eval t3 t3' ->
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero tm_zero) t2 t3) t2' /\
eval_many (tm_if (tm_iszero (tm_succ v)) t2 t3) t3'.
Proof.
intros v t2 t2' t3 t3' H.
destruct H as [ Hn [ He1 He2 ] ]. split.
apply m_three with
(t' := tm_if tm_true t2 t3) (t'' := t2).
apply e_if. apply e_iszerozero.
apply e_iftrue.
apply He1.
apply m_three with
(t' := tm_if tm_false t2 t3) (t'' := t3).
apply e_if. apply e_iszerosucc. apply Hn.
apply e_iffalse.
apply He2.
Qed.
Lemma two_values_sol : forall t u,
value t /\ value u ->
bvalue t \/
bvalue u \/
(nvalue t /\ nvalue u).
Proof.
unfold value. intros t u H.
destruct H as [ [ Hb1 | Hn1 ] H2 ].
left. apply Hb1.
destruct H2 as [ Hb2 | Hn2 ].
right. left. apply Hb2.
right. right. split.
apply Hn1.
apply Hn2.
Qed.
Lemma m_trans_sol : forall t u v,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many u v ->
eval_many t v.
Proof.
intros t u v Hm1 Hm2. induction Hm1.
apply Hm2.
apply m_step with (t' := t').
apply H.
apply IHHm1. apply Hm2.
Qed.
Lemma eval_rtc_many_sol : forall t u,
eval_rtc t u ->
eval_many t u.
Proof.
intros t u Hr. induction Hr.
apply m_one. apply H.
apply m_refl.
apply m_trans with (t' := u).
apply IHHr1.
apply IHHr2.
Qed.
Lemma eval_many_rtc_sol : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_rtc t u.
Proof.
intros t u Hm. induction Hm.
apply r_refl.
apply r_trans with (u := t').
apply r_eval. apply H.
apply IHHm.
Qed.
Lemma full_eval_to_value_sol : forall t v,
full_eval t v ->
value v.
Proof.
intros t v Hf. induction Hf.
apply H.
apply IHHf2.
apply IHHf2.
right. apply n_succ. apply H.
right. apply n_zero.
right. apply H.
left. apply b_true.
left. apply b_false.
Qed.
Lemma value_can_expand_sol : forall v,
value v ->
exists u, eval u v.
Proof.
intros v Hv. exists (tm_if tm_true v v). apply e_iftrue.
Qed.
Lemma exists_iszero_nvalue_sol : forall t,
(exists nv, nvalue nv /\ eval_many t nv) ->
exists bv, eval_many (tm_iszero t) bv.
Proof.
intros t [ nv [ Hnv Hm ]]. destruct Hnv.
exists tm_true.
apply m_trans with (t' := tm_iszero tm_zero).
apply m_iszero. apply Hm.
apply m_one. apply e_iszerozero.
exists tm_false.
apply m_trans with (t' := tm_iszero (tm_succ t0)).
apply m_iszero. apply Hm.
apply m_one. apply e_iszerosucc. apply Hnv.
Qed.
Lemma normal_form_to_forall_sol : forall t,
normal_form t ->
forall u, ~ eval t u.
Proof.
unfold normal_form, not. intros t H u He.
apply H. exists u. apply He.
Qed.
Lemma normal_form_from_forall_sol : forall t,
(forall u, ~ eval t u) ->
normal_form t.
Proof.
unfold normal_form, not. intros t H [ t' Het' ].
apply H with (u := t'). apply Het'.
Qed.
Lemma negation_exercise_sol : forall v1 v2,
~ (value v1 \/ value v2) ->
~ (~ bvalue v1 /\ ~ bvalue v2) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
intros v1 v2 H1 H2. destruct H2.
split.
intros Hb. destruct H1. left. left. apply Hb.
intros Hb. destruct H1. right. left. apply Hb.
Qed.
Lemma equality_exercise_sol : forall t1 t2 t3 u1 u2 u3 u4,
tm_if t1 t2 t3 = tm_if u1 u2 u2 ->
tm_if t1 t2 t3 = tm_if u3 u3 u4 ->
t1 = u4.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 t3 u1 u2 u3 u4 Heq1 Heq2.
inversion Heq1. subst t1. subst t2. subst t3.
inversion Heq2. reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma succ_not_circular_sol : forall t,
t <> tm_succ t.
Proof.
intros t. induction t.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq. destruct IHt. apply H0.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
Qed.
Lemma inversion_exercise_sol : forall t,
normal_form t ->
eval_many (tm_pred t) tm_zero ->
nvalue t.
Proof.
intros t Hnf Hm. inversion Hm. subst. inversion H.
apply n_zero.
apply n_succ. apply H2.
destruct Hnf. exists t'0. apply H2.
Qed.
Lemma contradictory_equalities_exercise_sol :
(exists t, exists u, exists v,
value t /\
t = tm_succ u /\
u = tm_pred v) ->
eval tm_true tm_false.
Proof.
intros [ t [ u [ v [ [ Hb | Hn ] [ eq1 eq2 ] ] ] ] ].
destruct Hb.
inversion eq1.
inversion eq1.
destruct Hn.
inversion eq1.
inversion eq1. subst t. subst u. inversion Hn.
Qed.
Lemma eval_fact_exercise_sol : forall t1 t2,
eval (tm_iszero (tm_pred t1)) t2 ->
eval t2 tm_false ->
exists u, t1 = tm_succ u.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 He1 He2. inversion He1. subst t2.
inversion He2. subst t'.
inversion H0. exists (tm_succ t0). reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma normal_form_if_sol : forall t1 t2 t3,
normal_form (tm_if t1 t2 t3) ->
t1 <> tm_true /\ t1 <> tm_false /\ normal_form t1.
Proof.
intros t1 t2 t3 Hnf. destruct t1.
destruct Hnf. exists t2. apply e_iftrue.
destruct Hnf. exists t3. apply e_iffalse.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. destruct Hnf. exists (tm_if t' t2 t3).
apply e_if. apply He.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. inversion He.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. destruct Hnf. exists (tm_if t' t2 t3).
apply e_if. apply He.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. destruct Hnf. exists (tm_if t' t2 t3).
apply e_if. apply He.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
split.
intros Heq. inversion Heq.
intros [t' He]. destruct Hnf. exists (tm_if t' t2 t3).
apply e_if. apply He.
Qed.
Lemma full_eval_from_value_sol : forall v w,
value v ->
full_eval v w ->
v = w.
Proof.
intros v w Hv Hf. induction Hf.
reflexivity.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
rewrite -> IHHf.
reflexivity.
right. apply value_succ_nvalue. apply Hv.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
destruct Hv as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
Qed.
Lemma value_is_normal_form_sol : forall v,
value v ->
normal_form v.
Proof.
intros v [ Hb | Hn ] [ t He ].
destruct Hb; inversion He.
generalize dependent t.
induction Hn; intros u He; inversion He; subst.
destruct (IHHn t'). apply H0.
Qed.
Theorem eval_deterministic_sol : forall t t' t'',
eval t t' ->
eval t t'' ->
t' = t''.
Proof.
intros t t' t'' He1. generalize dependent t''.
induction He1; intros t'' He2; inversion He2; subst.
reflexivity.
inversion H3.
reflexivity.
inversion H3.
inversion He1.
inversion He1.
rewrite -> (IHHe1 t1'0).
reflexivity.
apply H3.
rewrite -> (IHHe1 t'0).
reflexivity.
apply H0.
reflexivity.
inversion H0.
reflexivity.
assert (normal_form (tm_succ t)) as Hnf.
apply nvalue_is_normal_form. apply n_succ. apply H.
destruct Hnf. exists t'. apply H1.
inversion He1.
assert (normal_form (tm_succ t'')) as Hnf.
apply nvalue_is_normal_form. apply n_succ. apply H0.
destruct Hnf. exists t'. apply He1.
rewrite -> (IHHe1 t'0).
reflexivity.
apply H0.
reflexivity.
inversion H0.
reflexivity.
assert (normal_form (tm_succ t)) as Hnf.
apply nvalue_is_normal_form. apply n_succ. apply H.
destruct Hnf. exists t'. apply H1.
inversion He1.
assert (normal_form (tm_succ t0)) as Hnf.
apply nvalue_is_normal_form. apply n_succ. apply H0.
destruct Hnf. exists t'. apply He1.
rewrite -> (IHHe1 t'0).
reflexivity.
apply H0.
Qed.
Lemma eval_full_eval_sol : forall t t' v,
eval t t' ->
full_eval t' v ->
full_eval t v.
Proof.
intros t t' v He. generalize dependent v. induction He.
intros v Hf. apply f_iftrue.
apply f_value. left. apply b_true.
apply Hf.
intros v Hf. apply f_iffalse.
apply f_value. left. apply b_false.
apply Hf.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
subst. inversion H.
inversion H0.
inversion H0.
subst. apply f_iftrue.
apply IHHe. apply H3.
apply H4.
subst. apply f_iffalse.
apply IHHe. apply H3.
apply H4.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
subst. apply f_succ.
apply value_succ_nvalue. apply H.
apply IHHe. apply f_value. right.
apply value_succ_nvalue. apply H.
subst. apply f_succ.
apply H0.
apply IHHe. apply H1.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf. apply f_predzero.
apply f_value. right. apply n_zero.
intros v Hf. assert (t = v).
apply full_eval_from_value_sol.
right. apply H.
apply Hf.
subst v. apply f_predsucc.
apply H.
apply f_succ.
apply H.
apply Hf.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
subst. destruct H as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
subst. apply f_predzero. apply IHHe. apply H0.
subst. apply f_predsucc.
apply H0.
apply IHHe. apply H1.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf. apply f_iszerozero.
apply f_value. right. apply n_zero.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
apply f_iszerosucc with (v := t).
apply H.
apply f_value. right. apply n_succ. apply H.
intros v Hf. inversion Hf.
subst. destruct H as [ Hb | Hn ].
inversion Hb.
inversion Hn.
subst. apply f_iszerozero. apply IHHe. apply H0.
subst. apply f_iszerosucc with (v := v0).
apply H0.
apply IHHe. apply H1.
Qed.
Lemma full_eval_complete_sol : forall t v,
value v ->
eval_many t v ->
full_eval t v.
Proof.
intros t v Hv Hm. induction Hm.
apply f_value. apply Hv.
apply eval_full_eval_sol with (t' := t').
apply H.
apply IHHm. apply Hv.
Qed.
Lemma pred_not_circular_sol : forall t,
t <> tm_pred t.
Proof.
intros t H. induction t; inversion H; auto.
Qed.
Lemma m_succ_sol : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_succ t) (tm_succ u).
Proof.
intros t u Hm.
induction Hm; eauto using m_refl, m_step, e_succ.
Qed.
Lemma m_pred_sol : forall t u,
eval_many t u ->
eval_many (tm_pred t) (tm_pred u).
Proof.
intros t u Hm.
induction Hm; eauto using m_refl, m_step, e_pred.
Qed.
Fixpoint interp (t : tm) {struct t} : tm :=
match t with
| tm_true => tm_true
| tm_false => tm_false
| tm_if t1 t2 t3 =>
match interp t1 with
| tm_true => interp t2
| tm_false => interp t3
| t4 => tm_if t4 t2 t3
end
| tm_zero => tm_zero
| tm_succ t1 => tm_succ (interp t1)
| tm_pred t1 =>
match interp t1 with
| tm_zero => tm_zero
| tm_succ t2 =>
match tm_to_nat t2 with
| some_nat _ => t2
| no_nat => tm_pred (tm_succ t2)
end
| t2 => tm_pred t2
end
| tm_iszero t1 =>
match interp t1 with
| tm_zero => tm_true
| tm_succ t2 =>
match tm_to_nat t2 with
| some_nat _ => tm_false
| no_nat => tm_iszero (tm_succ t2)
end
| t2 => tm_iszero t2
end
end.
Lemma tm_to_bool_dom_includes_bvalue_sol : forall bv,
bvalue bv -> exists b, tm_to_bool bv = some_bool b.
Proof.
intros bv H. destruct H.
exists true. reflexivity.
exists false. reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma tm_to_bool_dom_only_bvalue_sol : forall bv b,
tm_to_bool bv = some_bool b -> bvalue bv.
Proof.
intros bv b Heq. destruct bv.
apply b_true.
apply b_false.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
Qed.
Lemma tm_to_nat_dom_includes_nvalue_sol : forall v,
nvalue v -> exists n, tm_to_nat v = some_nat n.
Proof.
intros v Hnv. induction Hnv.
exists O. reflexivity.
destruct IHHnv as [ n Heq ]. exists (S n).
simpl. rewrite -> Heq. reflexivity.
Qed.
Lemma tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue_sol : forall v n,
tm_to_nat v = some_nat n -> nvalue v.
Proof.
intros v. induction v; intros n Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
apply n_zero.
apply n_succ.
simpl in Heq. destruct (tm_to_nat v).
inversion Heq. eapply IHv. reflexivity.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
inversion Heq.
Qed.
Lemma interp_reduces_sol : forall t,
eval_many t (interp t).
Proof.
intros t. induction t.
apply m_refl.
apply m_refl.
simpl. destruct (interp t1).
eapply m_trans.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
eapply m_trans.
eapply m_one. apply e_iftrue.
apply IHt2.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
eapply m_trans.
eapply m_one. apply e_iffalse.
apply IHt3.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_if. apply IHt1.
apply m_refl.
simpl. apply m_succ. apply IHt.
simpl. destruct (interp t).
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_one. apply e_predzero.
remember (tm_to_nat t0) as x. destruct x.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_one. apply e_predsucc.
eapply tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue.
rewrite <- Heqx. reflexivity.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
apply m_pred. apply IHt.
simpl. destruct (interp t).
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_one. apply e_iszerozero.
remember (tm_to_nat t0) as x. destruct x.
eapply m_trans.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_one. apply e_iszerosucc.
eapply tm_to_nat_dom_only_nvalue.
rewrite <- Heqx. reflexivity.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
apply m_iszero. apply IHt.
Qed.
Lemma interp_fully_reduces_sol : forall t,
normal_form (interp t).
Proof.
induction t; intros [t' H].
inversion H.
inversion H.
simpl in H. destruct (interp t1).
destruct IHt2. eauto.
destruct IHt3. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
destruct IHt1. inversion H. eauto.
inversion H.
destruct IHt. inversion H. eauto.
simpl in H. destruct (interp t).
inversion H. inversion H1.
inversion H. inversion H1.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H.
remember (tm_to_nat t0) as x. destruct x.
destruct IHt. exists (tm_succ t').
apply e_succ. apply H.
inversion H; subst.
destruct (tm_to_nat_dom_includes_nvalue t')
as [n Heq].
apply H1.
rewrite <- Heqx in Heq. inversion Heq.
destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
simpl in H. destruct (interp t).
inversion H. inversion H1.
inversion H. inversion H1.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H.
remember (tm_to_nat t0) as x. destruct x.
inversion H.
inversion H; subst.
destruct (tm_to_nat_dom_includes_nvalue t0)
as [n Heq].
apply H1.
rewrite <- Heqx in Heq. inversion Heq.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
inversion H. destruct IHt. eauto.
Qed.
(* vi:set tw=64:
Local Variables:
fill-column: 64
End:
*)
Sign up for free to join this conversation on GitHub. Already have an account? Sign in to comment